Searle, Chalmers, and the Causal Power of Consciousness.(REVISED) Dear Jeff. Aug 6, 1999 I have looked over, as I promised, Searle's "The Mystery of Consciousness", and his attack therein on Chalmers. They come to a similar main conclusion, which, in accordance with our own position, is that consciousness is not logically or ontologically reducible to the objective aspects of nature. But then why does Searle attack Chalmers? Searle bases his position on the common sense judgements that "we know", first of all, that consciousness exists, and is different from the objective aspects of nature, such as our bodies and brains, which persist when we're asleep; and, secondly, that "brains cause consciousness" and, reciprocally, that consciousness can cause bodily actions: felt pain can cause the verbal report `ouch'. The point here is not that we absolutely "know" these things with 100% certainty: no such certainty exists. For scientists the point is rather that we must start our theorizing somewhere, and these premises are so reasonable, a priori, as to cast very serious doubt upon any premises that lead to conclusions that contradict them. Eventually the different alternative possible sets of premises that we use to guide our research must be judged a posteriori, on the basis of their practical success. But in the present embryonic state of the theory of the mind-brain connection we must rely on a priori criteria to guide our research. Chalmers says that Searle's mantra, `brains cause consciousness', "is entirely compatible with my views", "settles almost nothing", and "is simply a statement of the problem, not a solution". The first point here is that the causal connection FROM brain TO consciousness is not really in question: none of the principal positions deny it. The problem is the action of brain upon consciousness. Here Searle is clear: the pain cause the person to say `ouch', or to report " my continuing introspection of my feelings allow me to report, truthfully, that an experience of a painful finger exists `now' ". Similarly, Chalmers claims that his position is NOT epiphenomenalism. Yet both philosophers SEEM to want to remain within classical physical theory, and this theory SEEMS to entail epiphenomenalism. So the key questions to be asked of them are: (1) Do you accept the adequacy of classical physical theory for understanding the relationship between brain and consciousness? (2) Do you accept that consciousness can CAUSE behaviour, such as a verbal report of the continuing presence of the feeling of a painful finger? (3) If your answers to these two questions are YES, then how do you reconcile your affirmative answer to question (2) with a core idea of classical physical theory. which is that the objective world described by classical physical theory is, by itself, causally complete. I would insist that some cogent answer to this third question must be part of any adequate theory of the mind-brain connection that answers the first two questions affirmatively. Chalmers, in his section on "Strategies for avoiding epiphenonenalism" throws out some suggestions, but they all effectively reject the precepts of classical physical theory, as that theory is normally understood. The two core ideas of contemporary classical physical theory are: (1) Causal Explanation, with causation propagated by physical contact between locally defined objectively existing parts. (2) The dynamical completeness of this objective causal structure. Chalmers' suggestions for how to avoid epiphenomenalism seem violate these classical precepts, and move in the direction of orthodox quantum theory by making consciousness primary. Searle faces this key issue of how one can avoid epiphenomenalism, by simply asserting that consciousness is connected to the objective aspects by causal connections in both directions. But if one accepts both the causal efficacy of our thoughts and the main precept of classical physics, namely dynamical completeness within the domain of local objective properties, then: There would be two kinds of causal chains connecting certain physical properties, the first kind of chain confined wholly to the objective domain, in accordance with the principles of classical physics, and the other acting through consciousness via the claimed two-way causal connections. This situation is NOT analogous to the causal efficacy of hurricanes and of heat, where, due to the *reducibility* of all the pertinent macroproperties to microproperties, the macroscopically and microscopically described causal chains are basically the same causal connection, expressed in two different ways. But the *irreduciblity* of consciousness to the physical---proved by Chalmers for the case that "the physical" is essentially like what classical physical theory says it is--- blocks such a reduction in the case of consciousness. Barring some `mystical' connection that somehow makes these two logically and ontologically different causal chains equivalent, when applied to chains that connect physical facts to physical facts, we have a basic incompatility between contemporary classical physical theory, with its basic idea of causation only via contact between localized neighbors, and the assertion that there is a two-way causal connection between ideas and actions. This conclusion boils down to the fact that classical physical theory makes consciousness epiphenomenal, in the sense that the precepts of classical physical theory render any causal effect of consciousness on the physical world completely superfluous and ineffectual, because the effect is already caused by purely objective aspects acting alone. This problem was recognized already in the seventeenth century, and is the core of the mind-brain problem. But strenuous efforts have been made by philosophers during this century to get around this problem by reducing mind to matter: i.e., by trying to pass to some form of materialism or physicalism, which denies the idea that the facts of consciousness are EXTRA FACT, not entailed by the physical facts. Chalmers shows that IF ONE ACCEPTS THE NOTION OF "THE PHYSICAL" THAT IS EXEMPLIFIED BY CLASSICAL PHYSICAL THEORY, then the facts about conscious are not LOGICALLY/CONCEPTUALLY entailed by the physical: the facts of consciousness are, conceptually, EXTRA FACTS. Some extra "natural laws" must be added to fix the linkage: the connection between these two logically/conceptually separate worlds is not fixed by their defining concepts alone. On the other hand, if one accepts the idea of "THE PHYSICAL" that arises from orthodox quantum theory (i.e., von Neumann/Wigner quantum theory) where the "THE PHYSICAL" aspect of nature is the objective evolving state of knowledge represented in quantum theory by the evolving quantum state of the universe, then the subjective experiences DO supervene on "THE PHYSICAL". So the ideas of "physicalism", but not "materialism", turn out to be OK, within orthodox quantum theory. Searle's way of addressing the problem of epiphenomenalism is to down play the lack of an appropriate LOGICAL connection between consciousness and brain, and stress rather the presence of the CAUSAL connections, which Chalmers separates out in terms of psycho-physical laws. But I do not think that this solves the epiphenomenalism problem: if, as claimed by the precepts of classical physical theory, the objective world is already causally complete, then the causal chains via the subjective aspect of nature are superfluous and ineffectual. Searle stressed at the beginning of his book the need to abandon the obsolete traditional categories. But he did not emphasize that abandoning these obsolete categories means abandoning the classical physical theory that embodies them. I suspect that Searle's failure to emphasize this point is a key reason why his critics fail to understand him: they continue tacitly to think in terms of a classical-physics conception of physical reality that embodies the obsolete concepts that Searle has abandoned. So both Chalmers and Searle are actually rejecting the precepts of classical physical theory, although neither seems able to recognize or admit this fact, as did Wm. James before them: "...understand how great is the darkness in which we grope, and never forget that the the natural-science assumptions with which we started are provisional and revisable things." Does abandoning classical physics mean abandoning contemporary physics? Not at all! Searle's two premises are: (1) ontologically subjectively consciousness is ontologically different from the ontologically objective aspect of nature, and (2) there is a two-way causal connection between the ontologically subjective (i.e., experiential) aspects of nature and the ontologically objective aspects These premises are completely in line with (orthodox vN/W) quantum theory, where each conscious experience is an increment in knowledge that is connected to some particular individual physical system, and the physical state of the universe is an objective compendium of all these individual increments. This state is represented (in relativistic quantum field theory) by a structure consisting of a assembly of microscopically localized elements. ------------------------------------------------------------------- ------------------------------------------------------------------