From: THEORM::STAPP 27-JUN-1997 16:40:39.57 To: @KLEINLIST.DIS CC: STAPP Subj: Re: Nothing Buttery Dear Aaron, June 27, 1997 I thank you for your detailed message "Nothing Buttery". It deserves a detailed reply. Indeed, I think it addresses the core issue of the mind-matter problem: others who argue that mind lies outside classically conceived matter may formulate their arguments in terms of "supervenience", instead of "nothing but", but I think the point can be better made in terms of "nothing but". I have included the phrase "classically conceived" in front of "matter" because otherwise the whole issue becomes: "What is matter?" or "What does `The Physical' mean?" It is conceivable that--- contrary to the ideas upon which classical physics is based---matter is basically mind-like, or is fundamentally entwined with mind right from the start. Thus one must specify what "matter" means if the mind-matter problem to be well defined: there would be no problem if matter were mind. I think nonphysicists generally fail adequately to appreciate that modern physics gives us, at the fundamental level, an idea of matter that is very different from the classical one, and hence that it is absolutely essential to say, in this context, what "matter" is supposed to mean: certainly a "matter" whose basic law of evolution is formulated in terms of our thoughts is essentially different from classically conceived matter, so a construal of "matter" in this `modern' way changes completely the philosophical character of the mind-matter problem. Back to "nothing but": Although the argument can be formulated more abstract the point is made most clearly, I think, by going directly to the root level of ontology versus epistemology: i.e., "the physically real" versus "our concepts". Things can be specified cleanly here because the ontology in question is the ontology of classical mechanics. Consequently, since we know that the CM ontology is actually completely false, we do not have to squabble, in formulating a CM ontology, over such irresolvable questions as what "nature herself is really like": answers to such questions lie forever outside the realm of human (scientifically acquired) knowledge. All our deliberations are within the realm of human concepts, which we are free to organize as we see fit to meet our needs, which I assume here to be the need to rationally understand ourselves and the world we seem to inhabit. In particular, we are *free to define* the classical ontology in any way that gives a lean but adequate rational foundation for both classical mechanics and epistemology. I want to start with, and justify using, the austere CM ontology according to which the physical world consists of "nothing but" the positions, velocities, and masses of some finite collection of structureless bits of matter that influence only their immediate neighbors. The entire classical dynamics is specified (over a large but finite spacetime region) by considering, separately and independently, each of a very large but finite set of very tiny (overlapping) spacetime regions: one can imagine an independent deity's being in charge of each of these tiny spacetime regions, and knowing nothing about anything outside that region, but following a set of rigidly specified laws for constructing the motions of the particles in his tiny realm. The totality of what is known to "Nature" is just the disjunctive aggregration what is known to these individual deities, each of which is conceived of as living "incommunicado". Thus Nature, in this conception of it, cannot know that there are three apples in a certain basket, because having that knowledge would require some sort of communication among the `deities', or some sort of "overseer" that can know what's in the minds of several deities. But the principles of classical mechanics (in particular the locality principle of classical relativistic field theory) tell us precisely the there is no need for any such communication, or any such overseer: the classical dynamical evolution of the universe can be specified without allowing any such communications, or having any such overseer. I have spelled out in my book, and will not repeat here, a classical picture of brain functioning in terms of patterns of brain activities (neuronal activities?) that I called "symbols", because within the context of the brain in which they are imbedded each one has dispositions to excite other symbols. And I suggested how these symbols would be organized into templates for action, and how they would connect to sensory inputs and motor outputs so that the classically described organism could be expected to behave roughly in the way human beings behave. Our conscious experiences are then to be associated with the occurrence of these templates for action, and they consist of the `feelings of the initiation of the actions' that the template for action initiates. (Some of these actions might be to record answers to certain questions about the character of one's sensings.) These knowings are quite different from Nature's knowings because on the small scale the human knowings are far less detailed, but, unlike Nature's knowings, they can combine information coming from different microscopic regions. Now where does mathematics and number theory fit into this ontology-epistemology? Evidently each of the deities is required to have enormous mathematical capacity: even to write down one component of the position of one particle would, in general, be beyond the capacity of all the people who ever lived, or ever will live, aided by all the computers that they will ever build. [The fantastic computing abilities assigned to nature by classical mechanics are so prodigious as to make it seem almost "obvious", on the basis of that alone, that the classical picture could not actually be correct, but that question is not the issue here.] On the other hand, the repertory of manipulations that these deities are required to master is very limited: they need never understand "greater than", or "less than" or "integer", or "subset of a set", or "denumerable set" or "prime number": they only need to know how to integrate differential equations, which can, with only indetectable error, be replaced by finite difference equations, on some sufficiently fine scale. If we also allow some truncation of the numbers then we can reduce the whole classical ontology (over the finite spacetime region) to just a huge battery of imagined computers each of which needs to be able to do nothing but simple arithmetic, and never does anything but simple arithmetic calculations involving numbers pertaining to some associated tiny spacetime region. There is no communication between any two computers beyond the common access of neighboring computers to certain common numbers. I would like to defend the idea that the austere classical-physics ontolgy that I have just outlined does make sense, as a "nothing but" ontology that provides a rational basis for physics and epistemology: the physical world is conceived of as consisting of "nothing but" this horde of simple idealized computers, each one behaving in the way needed to determine the sets of numbers that will define the trajectories of "structureless bits of matter" in the way prescribed by the laws of classical mechanics. If X_1 is the X coordinate of particle 1, and X_2 is the X coordinate of a far-away particle 2, say at time t=0, them the number X_1 exists in the physical world (according to this austere conception of the physical world) and X_2 exists in the physical world. But (X_1 + X_2) does not: there is a register that contains the number X_1, and a register that contains the number X_2, but no register, in the set of all registers that are needed to define the physical world (in this conception of the physical world), that contains the number that is defined as the sum of X_1 and X_2. [If some devices were designed to try to measure X_1 and X_2 and to put the sum of these numbers, represented by some physical configuration of readings of the basic registers, into the physical system, then to the extent that such devices were actually built, and actually did perform as they were supposed to, one would have an exception to the assertion made above, but such exceptions would be exceedingly rare, and, in view of the practical difficulties, undoubtedly of zero likelihood to actually occur] Of course, all we can ever think about is our thoughts, so some care is needed to distinguish the ontological physical reality---as it is conceived of in this austere ontology, which consists only of a set of numbers each of which is supposed to be stored in some one of the registers specified in the model---and a conception that someone living in that world could have of that world: this latter conception could in principle include a conception of the sum (X_1 + X_2). Thus physicists and mathematicians are able to do all of the mathematical manipulations that they have invented or devised for manipulating their conceptions of possible classical worlds of the kind specified by the austere classical ontology. I have discussed at length---in my earlier discussions with Pat Hayes--- how the classical conception, being built on idealizations of (mainly visual) sense impressions is such that someone can compare his conceptualizations of the physical world to his sense impresssions and make judgements that would bring his conception of the world into rough coordination with the classical world that is supposed to exist, according to this ontology, and how our language grows to accommodate refinements connected to the various physical sciences (e.g., biology). So where, in all of this, is the verity that you speak of, namely that 29 is prime and 30 is not. More generally, where is number theory? Is it part of the physical world, or merely conceptual: i.e., an aspect of thoughts about numbers? The verities of number theory certainly do not lie in the austerely conceived classical world specified by this ontology: there is, in the horde of computers that define, in this ontology, what is part of physical reality none that uses, or stores in any register, the assertion that 29 is prime or that 30 is not. This model ontology shows that the properties of numbers NOT NEEDED to perform the simple arithmetic operations required to work out the classical dynamical evolution can be consistently regarded as not being part of the austerely conceived classical physical world: most of number theory is conceptual; it resides in realms of thought, and to the extent that thoughts and concepts lie only in minds associated with physical entities, as naturalistic philosophy demands, most of number theory exists only in minds associated with physical entities. More relevant to the present discussion is the fact that (X_1 + X_2) is, in the same sense, conceptual, not physical. If one were to accept that this sum, which---according to this austere ontology---exists only in minds, and not in the austerely conceived world of classically conceived matter, were actual part of the physical world one would, by virtue of this single simple error, bring chaos into one's thinking, because every other claim that some conceptual thing is part of the physical world could be justified by citing its similarity to this case: in logic the admission of one error, however minute, causes the whole structure to collapse in ruins. It is useful to introduce, in contrast to the austere classical physics ontology, another concept: the subtle classical physics ontology. The point is this: if we accept a naturalistic philosophy then the minds are to be associated with physical structures, or systems, and we might as well, for definiteness, focus on human beings, considered as body/brains, with minds somehow associated. The conceptual things discussed above (e.g., prime numbers, (X_1 + X_2), concepts and words pertaining to biology, and recognizable and nameable perceptions) are supposed to be associated in some way with activities in the body/brains of these human beings. So there is some subtle way in which these concepts "belong" to the material world: various dispositions exist in these body/brains that make it possible for learned discourse about these concepts to occur between properly prepared body/brains. Taking, for simplicity, an electrical curcuit analogy, the array of resistances, impedances, inductances, and capacitances is arranged so that system of curcuits is able to engage in learned discourse about properties of prime numbers etc.. Hence this part of number theory, namely the ability of physical systems to discourse learnedly about it, is "in the classical physical system" in this subtle way. So we now have in place, in quite concrete terms, the essential elements of the mind-matter problem: the austere CM ontology that is basically a "nothing but" ontology; our concepts, as we human beings experience/feel them; and the subtle imbeddings of our concepts in the high-level physical properties and activities of, in particular, certain biological systems that we call members of the species "homo sapiens". Within this framework we can consider the points made in your "Nothing Buttery" message. The issue is how causal mechanisms in our brain are related to our conscious experiences. You approach this problem by emphasizing that we are dealing with a complex situation that can probably be profitably analyzed by thinking in terms of a hierarchy of mechanisms, with higher-level mechanisms implemented in lower-level ones. I certainly concur that this way of thinking should be useful, and believe that nature, both biological and physical, seems to be constructed like this. As regards the physical, let me recall that it was only during this century that the atomic hypothesis became generally accepted (as a consequence of the analysis of brownian motion) and in this century we have seen evidence for several deeper levels (elementary particles and quarks, with more probably to come). You argue, and I would agree, that the idea of "nothing but" is a bad idea if it is construed as entailing the non-utility of an analysis of brain function in terms of a hierarchy of mechanisms. For the brain activities associated most closely with mind may be the activities of a brain mechanism that rides on other brain mechanisms. However, I would stress that this analysis is being done by someone, perhaps by you. And that analysis is conceptual: you can do a tremendous amount of analysis without building a single exemplar. But let me grant that in the case at hand we are contemplating and analyzing a really existing physical system that is best conceived of as consisting of a hierarchy of mechanisms. And, to get to the point, let us suppose that that system is a human brain that is "having" conscious experiences. And let me grant that your hierarchical analysis of the causal structure of the brain activity is apparently giving us a satisfactory account of what seems to be happening in the brain. And suppose this brain activity is "correlated" with the conscious experiences that this brain is "having" in just the way specified by a codification of empirical results on the NCC (neural correlates of conscious) formulated by Crick, Koch, Klein et. al.. Then one can ask: What is this relationship "having" that connects the physical brain activities---that your heirarchical causal theory may seem adequately to explain---to the conscious experiences that are associated empirically with those brain activities? My answer is that there is here, from the theoretical point of view, a logical gap between the austere CM ontological concept of the brain activity and the associated conscious experience. The physical activities of the brain are asserted to be, fundamentally, "nothing but" the motions of structureless bits of matter, but the classical conception of these sets of motions is too impoverished to allow the existence any such set of motions to logically entail, by virtue of the specified concepts, the existence of, say, an actual experience of a patch of "green". But if consciousness is not logically entailed by an ontology that entails the dynamics prescribed by the classical laws then consciousness can be left out without affecting the physical world: it is therefore epiphenomenal. You replied: >If you really think I am talking about the addition of any ad hoc >epiphenomenal appendage then I have totally failed to communicate in the >last couple of months, especially in all my claims that I want something >stronger than mere correlation between ontological layers, though not >necessarily as strong as mathematical or logical implication. > >I keep saying I am talking about an implementation relation between two >equally real ontological levels, but where one X is implemented in the >other Y (X supervenes on Y). If such a thing is possible for mechanisms >then saying the system is "nothing but" Y, simply ignores the existence >and causal powers of X. > >If you have an argument that it is impossible for any new ontology, >including new causal powers, to be implemented in a configuration of >dynamically interacting physical components, lets hear it. Until then >the use of "nothing but" is without any foundation. > >To just brush that aside and say that if Y is a physical system then it >is "nothing but" a physical system is either to mistake a trivial >tautology for a profound truth, or else to to beg the question of the >possibility of mechanism supervenenience. > >Whether and how such implementations are possible is what we have been >discussing all along. To simply *assume* that it is impossible is >just circular in this context. I appreciate that *you* are not talking about the addition of an ad hoc epiphenomenal appendage: that you are talking about a hierarchy of supervenient mechanical levels with causal powers. I have no problem anything you say insofar you do not assume CM. For my whole point concerns a problem with CM and consciousness. Insofar as you are accepting CM, and are talking about levels of structures *in the brain*, there is, in fact, NO CONFLICT between "nothing but" and "causal powers" of high-level structures: within the austere CM ontology the high-level structures in the brain will have causal powers precisely because of the arrangements of the matter in the brain, and the causal power of the thus-arranged matter. So I think we can agree that it is logically quite possible for there to be a hierarchical causal structure within the austere CM ontology---in which this causal structure is ontologically composed of "NOTHING BUT" these moving bits of matter---and that, moreover, anything over and above these moving bits of matter (including, of course, all the causal structures built out of them) is, as far as classical physics is concerned, gratuitous, and in fact, insofar as it is physical, is contrary to the CM conception of physical reality. So I am NOT ignoring the causal power of any structure in the brain by accepting the austere "nothing but" CM ontology: I am only insisting that whereas this "nothing but" ontology does account for all causal properties of the brain compatible with CM, it is too impoverished, in terms of its explicitly specified properties---which include all of the properties needed to account for all of CM---to demand, *under any conceivable configurational condition*, the existence of an experience of a patch of "green", which can therefore be left out without affecting or upsetting the causal structure that fixes the dynamical evolution of the physical. You wrote: >If you have an argument that it is impossible for any new ontology, >including new causal powers, to be implemented in a configuration of >dynamically interacting physical components, lets hear it. Until then >the use of "nothing but" is without any foundation. Well, it certainly is impossible for any new ontology that is compatible with the principles of CM to be added to the austere CM ontology, and to add new causal powers, except insofar as the additions are epiphenomenal with respect to all physical properties and activities. This is because the austere "nothing but" CM ontology that I have described specifies completely, in accordance with the dynamically complete principles of CM, the motions of all the bits of matter that constitute the physical reality of CM. One can add on all sorts extra ontology, ad infinitum, and add causal powers that will determine the behavior of these extra pieces. But these additions cannot alter the behavior of the parts covered by classical mechanics because the austere CM ontology already does that job completely. This completeness of classical mechanics is, of course, the core of the mind-matter problem. (I do not mean by this "completeness" that we necessarily know today all of the kinds of particles and fields that exist in nature: I mean by classical mechanics the general classical relativistic local-field framework, taken to be complete in the sense that all of the *existing* different types of fields and particles are supposed to be included, whether we human beings have yet discovered them or not) You wrote: >To just brush that aside and say that if Y is a physical system then it >is "nothing but" a physical system is either to mistake a trivial >tautology for a profound truth, or else to to beg the question of the >possibility of mechanism supervenenience. > >Whether and how such implementations are possible is what we have been >discussing all along. To simply *assume* that it is impossible is >just circular in this context. Again, the first question is whether CM is assumed to be valid. If it is then there is no possibility of a non-epiphenomenal supervenient mechanism: any added level can be left out without altering any physical activity or property because the austere ontology already fixes these activities and properties, yet is too impoverished, logically, to demand the existence of consciousness, which therefore cannot supervene upon the physical, since it can be left out without changing the physical. If classical mechanics is rejected then I think it rational to go to the replacement that physicists have already dicovered, and worked out, and confirmed experimentally in highly nontrivial ways to one part in a hundred million in some cases, and have never found to be violated, and to accept this replacement in the form that seems best able to the close the logical gap described above. You write: >Even if some of the possibilities consistent with the minimal >assumptions are "weird" there's nothing wrong with trying to see what >can be achieved with minimal assumptions. > >On the contrary, NOT doing that by starting from restrictive assumptions >is anti-scientific since it prevents the discovery of important new >features of the higher level mechanisms. I think the more reasonable program is try to stay within scientifically established tradition until some difficulty appears: otherwise the possibilities are just too unconstrained. When traditional ideas fail, their very failure give some clue as to how to proceed. I see no rational reason to reject the laboriously achieved findings of 300 years of physical science. >But we had better have a pretty clear idea what question we are asking, >and the formulation of the question, i.e. the definition of mentality, >had better not in itself assume anything about QM, otherwise the process >is circular, and ignores the fact that there was a serious question >being asked (e.g. by Kant, and many others) long before anyone knew >anything about QM. So it could not be a way of answering THAT question. You have argued before that good definitions come only when one has a theory. But, in any case, I characterize mind by feelings and experiencings, not by QM. QM could be a way of answering questions posed before QM was discovered because it provides a way of evading the overly stringent logical demands of CM without losing any of the valid predictions of CM, and it provides also an already created (by physicist) way of consistently introducing into physical reality our causally efficacious thoughts. >This leaves open the entirely different question whether, as you've >claimed, it is impossible to articulate QM fully without involving >consciousness, which seems so far to be the only remotely plausible >argument for linking the two. I never made such a strong claim. My argument is that CM is logically unsatisfactory because there is an uncloseable logical gap involving a lack of causal connection (epiphenomenalism), and this makes it reasonable to open one's eyes to the fact that physicists have already, on the basis empirical results, found CM to be fundamentally incorrect, and hugely so. And the (orthodox) physicists' replacement of CM did involve bringing conscious into physics, inspite of their extremely reluctance to do so. I have said that no alternative to the orthodox interpretation has claimed the allegiance of a majority of interested physicists/philosophers, and that the orthodox interpretation remains, in the absence of any lilly-white challenger, the uncomfortably-held standard view, any failure of which would be regarded as Nobel worthy, I am sure (in the good company of many ambitious experimentalists). >However, my impression is that this argument is being undermined by the >fact that whatever the leading physicists of the early 20th century may >have thought, the current physicist community is moving towards a view >that replaces notions of consciousness with notions of particular >physical configurations that in effect "make measurements". (E.g. see >the article on schroedinger's cat in the current Scientific American.) I do not believe the current physics community is moving toward any fixed view on this point. Many experiments are being performed and all results are in exact conformity with the predictions of the orthodox Copenhagen interpretation, which remains the simplest because it is based pragmatically upon what we human observers observe and report to each other. I think you have misinterpreted the Scientific American article. It touts Zurek's decoherence theory as if it were somehow essentially different from the orthodox interpretation when all it really is is a working out of some of the details of what the orthodox theory predicts: it does not claim to give any predictions that differ from what the orthodox theory says. Any empirical departures from the approximations that Zurek's equation represent would call for refinements that would be defined by the underlying orthodox interpretation. The parameters of the GRW theory were defined to give good agreement with the orthodox predictions: GRW would become significant if the orthodox predictions would fail, while those of GRW would work for some other values of the GRW parameters. But no failure of the orthodox predictions have ever been encountered. There is certainly still widespread dissatisfaction among physicists with the idea of bringing mind into physics, and many physicsts might opine that QM doesn't *really* bring in mind. But it certainly COULD, and I think that this possibility should be of great interest to anyone who is seriously interested in the mind-matter problem. Finally, a word about supervenience vs identity. My suggestion that you probably want to identify consciousness with certain characteristic (kinds of) brain behavior did not mean a one-to-one (identity) correspondence: it seems to me that *many* brain behaviours that represent similar causal relationships should be experienced in the same way: surely the failure of one single microchannel to open could hardly be expected to be able to be felt by anyone. Your emphasis on the fact that conscious experiences can be restricted in ways that the possible brain states are not is of prime importance to my QM theory. The situation is this: the problem with interpreting quantum theory without introducing mind is that there are no natural conditions within the mathematical structure itself to specify when and where collapses occur. Introducing consciousness gives one an external (to the mathematical formalism that is the QM generalization of CM) criterion: the collapse must be to a state that corresponds in an appropriate way to a possible experiential state: this restriction is the core of the Copenhagen interpretation, and it is needed to avoid what must otherwise be an ad hoc and arbitrary stipulation on the theory, and physicists abhor such things. And it simultaneously makes the theory eminently practical because the probabilities of the collapses are the only things that the theory cleanly predicts, and these collaspes are exactly what is, according to the theory, directly experienced. So theory and experiment are linked in an ideal fashion. This restriction on the possible collapses, via restrictions on possible experiences, is what injects experience PER SE into the brain dynamics. Thanks for giving me your nice letter to respond to. Your letter has greatly helped me to understand your position: I hope this letter will be similarly helpful to you. Best regards, Henry