Dear Pat, Thank you for your patient reply. I think I had understood your position before, but it probably helps to have it spelled out in the detail you did. Now I must try to make you understand why I believe I have answered your challenges. I'll try not to repeat. But a key point is Bohr's central point that the language of classical physics is a refinement of everyday language, which we use to tell each other what we have done and what we have learned. When I tell the technician to put that mirror at the place marked by X and a second mirror ten feet north of the first, I am using everyday language. Children learn what "dogs", and "cats" and "mirrors" are, and also what "ten feet" means. This all comes about through pointing, examples, and training, and is part of what it means to learn a language. This same common language is used by all the physical sciences to describe how to set up an experiment and how to describe the results. Of course, as the sciences evolve the languages evolve with them, so that today a technician knows what ten gauge copper wire means. But he has learned this in much the way he learned as a child what a spoon is. This common language of the physical sciences allows the scientists and technicians to set up experiments that conform to specifications and allows the observers to report the results. It involves ever more technically refined language. But the metalurgical specification of the materials from which a wire is made might be used by biologists and chemists and physiologists etc. You accuse Bohr of "conceptual myopia", but in this matter he was seeing things in a broad way, in the sense of encompassing all of science when he emphasized, in connection with experiments, the use of "everyday language suitably refined" to "tell each other what we have done and what we have learned". You speak of "scratching my nose" as an example of the kind of problem that arises. We learn as children what a "nose" is and what it means to "scratch" a nose. This is not part of a disconnected language of biology: any aborigines know what a "nose" is, and what the word for it is in his language. You cite the fact "leaves are green" as a fact *not* entailed by the classical physics theoretical description and principles. That may be true. Green might mean a psychological rather than spacetime form, and quantum theory is needed. If by "green" we mean only that the light from the leaf lands at a certain point after passing through a prism, then that fact is certainly specified by the complete classical description, because the complete classical description says exactly where all the energy is located. No extra vocabulary is involved in the description of the observed fact: i.e.,where the light lands. The fact specified by the classical physics description, namely that the light from the leaf "lights up a patch on the screen centered on a certain number, say 752, which is also labelled by the word "Green", is specified by the complete classical physics description, and the technician can announce to the scientific community that "the patch labeled `green' lighted up", in write this in his log book. In fact, one of the key episodes in the history of science revolved about this sort of fact, namely Newton's announcing of his results of experiments with sunlight and prisms; the retort of some philosopher that those results were absurd and impossible; and the confirmation of Newton's claim by countless scientists. If classical physics did describe the world then it would certainly have to account for the fact that the light from the leaf (or from every green leaf) is in fact green not red (i.e., gets deflected in the manner that characterizes green light, not red light). And the fact that the light lands where it does is something that can be reported in common everyday language by a child. I have spelled this out in detail because I am baffled by your remarks about the possibility of "red chlorophyll". This is certainly a place where some futher explanation is needed: I simply have no idea what all your remarks at this point are supposed to show. No extra "theory" is involved here. And nothing depends on what "I know" now or did not know about plant biology. If the classical theory were correct it would necessarily, by itself, entail where the light reflected off of any leaf would go if it were passed through a prism. This is simply because if the classical conception of nature were correct, then the complete classical physics description would specify where every bit of energy and matter is at every instant of time, and that would specify in particular where the light that is deflected throught the prism would land on the screen. I quite agree that once we know how experience is connected to the brain we will find zombies a ridiculuos idea: that is MY point! That is why the classical physics framework is unsatisfactory: it leads to this ridiculous idea. It leads to this ridiculous idea because the description provided by the classical physics description describes nothing but the dispositions of the particles and fields: the empirical connection of the "physical facts" specified by this classical physics description to the general realm of our experience is made by observers communicating `what they have done and what they have learned' to the community by means of everyday language, refined to take into account our expanding theoretical ideas about the world. But this empirically effected transfer of the facts represented in particle-and-fields description to the realm of experience of communicating scientists is not explained by the classical physical theory itself: there is this "expanatory gap". You admit that this gap exists, but claim that a similar gap exists for the physical sciences. Now an important point must be made here. If there is a gap in the normal classical laws of physics that allows the particle-and-fields to do whatever they actually do without experience being present then zombies would be possible, within the framework of the classical theory, regardless of whether or not `other gaps' exist. So this issue of `other possible gaps' is a red herring. You admit that the gap in question is present. So you should admit that Zombies are possible within the logical framework provided by the classical laws and concepts. Raising the issue of other possible gaps obfuscates this main point. But are there other explanatory gaps? Well, that depends on what you want to explain. Insofar as the classical conception is valid, there is a whole world of physical facts specified by (entailed by) the dispositions of the particles and fields at all times. This includes the changes and developments and evolutions of all physical systems. There is also all of our empirical ability to recognize various named spacetime configurations, and our ability to communicate to the scientific community what we have done in the way of setting up spacetime congigurations and what we have learned in terms of the appearance of recognizable named spacetime forms. All of these communications constitute a certain body of scientific knowledge that belongs to the scientific community, but that does not involve a gap of the kind mentioned above. I said: "So if our brains are included in the classical physics theoretical description of the physical world..." You objected: "But this begs the question! HOW can the concept of `brain' be included in a description in theoretical physics? (Where in physics is there any reference to `brains'?) To do this, one must provide an ACCOUNT of brains in sufficient detail to be able to translate brain-language into particle-and-field language. That translation constitutes the `bridging laws' we keep referring to, and it/they are NOT entailed by physics.... There is no `classical description of our brains' because the word `brain' is not part of the vocabulary of physics. ( Like you, I feel a sense of frustration. This point seem so obvious I cannot find a simpler way to express it, yet it seems not to get across.)" This point may lie at the root of our inability to communicate, so I shall pay attention to it. The `bridging principle' that *I* keep referring to is the one needed to bring consciousness in, not brains: I say that the complete classical physics theoretical description includes by definition the description of the location and velocity of every particle in the universe, and the value and rate of change of every field at every spacetime point. So the complete classical description includes, in particular, the description of the dispositions of all the particles and fields in anyone's skull, and this conglomerate consists chiefly of that person's brain. So it is true *by definition* that, according to the classical physics conceptualization of nature, the classical physics theoretical description of the universe includes the description of all the particle and fields in anyone's brain, and this description of all the particles and fields in a brain is what is called the description of that brain. No further theory of the brain is needed to establish this elemental fact that, according to the classical physics conceptualization, (the description of) each brain is included in the classical physics theoretical desription of the the universe. This fact has been true for three hundred years, long before this century's great advances in understanding the brain. Similarly, Newton was able to make predictions about the orbit of the earth, without having a theory of plate tectonics You say: " I still see NO REASON you have given to justify your firm belief that subjectivity differs from any other phenomenon, other that confidence in our future ignorance." This is one of your principal and oft-repeated assertions. So I must spell out my answer. You tie your assertion to your "red chlorophyll" discussion, and the idea of "other theories", and the possibilities of future advances in our knowledge. I certainly recognize that our everyday language evolves and becomes more refined, and is a giant web of interconnecting links tied into our realms of experience. And we can use these refinements to refine the experiments that we are able to specify and report upon. But I think it is a mistake to think that this common language can be usefully separated into disjoint parts: this language by means of which we communicate to each other what experiments we have set up and what results we have observed is an inseparable whole, based on everyday language. So I see no `other theories" or "changing theories" problem. In the classical conceptualization the physical sciences are tied together two ends. At one end there is the common physical foundation in the particles-and-fields that are supposed to be the physical ingredients from which everything physical is built: at the other end there is the linkage to the community of scientific thinkers, via their sense experiences and their refined common language. But I fail to see in any of this any gap of the kind that you admit is present in the case of consciousness. The essential REASON for the difference is that this latter gap is specifically linked to consciousness. It arises from the character of classical physical theory. That theory ties together everything that is built out of particles and fields into one highly coherent unified structure. But these laws and principles of classical physics do not bring consciouness into this tight structure that includes everything else. You always reply that these laws and principles also do not bring in such things such as brains, cells, cell walls. etc. etc.. But *the complete physical description* that these principles claim exists does, if the theory is correct, describe all the brains that are present in the universe, and all the cells and all the cell walls. And by our experiments we can learn about the spacetime structure that exist and are, if the classical conception is valid, entailed by the complete physical description. No big gap is encountered. But if one asks about the *experiential content* of the universe that is entailed by `the complete physical theoretical description' then the answer is "nothing at all", really. There is no entailment of consciousness. So the two kinds of properties, physical and experiential, enter very differently, due to the very different ways that they enter into the `complete classical physical description', namely completely entailed in the case of the physical and not entailed at all in the case of the experiential. In this connection I say later: "the classical physics description would---to the extent that it is true---give a complete physical description of all the physical facts about biological systems." You counter with: "Not without some account of how concepts such as `cell wall', etc. are connected to the language of physics. I'm still unclear whether you allow such accounts to be part of physics, or to be bridging laws that are somehow entailed by physics (which I think I can prove is logically impossible, given your own definition of `entailment' in terms of deduction.) or to be part of biology not but not of physics. If the latter then your claim in the last sentence above is manifestly false." So here we are at the heart of the matter! How do I answer? I am saying that---if the classical conception is correct---then the complete classical physical description would give a complete description of every physical fact and object that exists in the universe, and hence every `cell' and `cell wall', etc. to the extent that it is something physical. Now---according to the classical conceptualization--nature herself just does her thing, which is simply to unfold in accordance with the deterministic physical laws: in the process she makes what biologist call "cells", but she herself has no need to "define" exactly what a "cell" is, nor which of the sciences should concern itself with such things. Focus now on some clear example of a cell. According to the classical conceptualization it is---and has--some structure, which can be specified at the level of particles and fields. It will evolve and eventually disintegrate: the point at which it ceases to be a cell will depend on the exact definition of cell one chooses to use. In view of this ambiguity one sees that the physicist's description of it in terms of its evolving microscopic structure, and its interactions with its surroundings, is more informative than its limited specification in terms of certain arbitrary conventional terms: given the complete physical description one can see how all sort of possible higher-level (hence less informative) definitions would apply: one has the base information from which the special conventional definitions must draw. Consequently, the biologist's definitions can be regarded as basically secondary and derivative. They are useful to biologist and hence certainly are not to be ignored. But they are less informative in principle, and unsuitable for the basic ontology. You say: If you find it obvious that `physical biology' can account for our overt behaviour then... [PROVE IT] Proof: What I claim is obvious is that if the principles of classical mechanics were valid then the complete physical description in terms of particles and fields that these principles claim exists would completely specify our overt behaviours. This result is rigorous and obvious and trivially true because the complete physical description in terms of particles and fields specifies, according to the assumed principles, exactly where every particle and bit of energy is at every instant of time from the beginning of time to the end of time, and the assumed principles also assert that all physical objects are made up exclusively of these particles and bits of energy. But the behaviour of any system that is built exclusively out of tiny localized parts is determined by the changing locations and motions of these parts. You say in response to my claim: "I disagree, see above. This has been my central point ever since the beginning of this debate." Well, this certainly pinpoints a basic disagreement! It seems to me that you are simply wrong on this point about which there is no room for rational dispute. Best regards, Henry