Dear Pat, April 3, 1997 The new title (Principled Distinctions) is appropriate: it pinpoints the issue before us, which certainly is *the* critical issue, and it signalizes that we have moved---at last---beyond the stage of talking completely past each other. Although you do not yet see my main point, I think you will. By way of preparation let me first provide a little more background about where I am coming from, because I think your tendency to identify my position with one's you have heard before has been the main cause of our inability to communicate. I believe the position you usually contend against is based on an *implicit* acceptance of a `classical-type conception of nature', and that that position you oppose is not defencible, logically, until that implicit presumption is made explicit. However, once that implicit assumption is made explicit then that explicit `classical' premise does provide the rational basis for the needed principled distinction. The other key element in my own thinking, which is based mainly on my study of the lesson's taught by the Einstein-Bohr debate, is to see science as a human endeavour: as a social process in which our language and concepts evolve by trial and error, and by elaborations of hunches. It resides in the collection of conscious thoughts of the community of communicating human observers and scientists. The `observed facts' are represented within this body of thought by the articulated assertions of trained and qualified observers pertaining to what they have done and what they have learned. First some clean-up. I said: >the classical conception asserts that this `complete classical physical >description' does exist. You replied: "Really? Where is it supposed to be written, and in what language? Or perhaps you mean only a mathematical sense of 'exists': but then you should be a little more careful about what you mean by 'description'. My statement >the classical conception asserts that this `complete classical physical >description' does exist. stated in more detail would be this: the classical conception of nature asserts that there does exist a physical world that is in principle describable in the language of classical physics and that this existing world is part of a world history that extends from the infinite past to the infinite future and conforms to all of the principles and laws of classical physics. The precise form of these laws may or may not be known now to human beings, but they are in any case fixed in nature, and are similar in essence to contemporary classical physics. But the question is: How is this assumed physical world connected to our experiences, and to articulated facts about it? You say: "But I think we can put this subdebate to rest, since it seems to have been based on a misunderstanding about what 'the classical conception' means. Lets agree that it amounts to far more than classical PHYSICS, but includes a complete PAF description of the entire history of the universe from start to finish. "It still doesnt use the term 'leaf', notice. However, I think I comprehend you now rather better. Your point, if I finally comprehend it, is not that this complete description entails any macroscopic descriptions, but rather that it entails that the trained observers (who are themselves part of the described PAF plenum) will report their observations in a certain way:" ... "So it is the OBSERVERS BEHAVIOR which would be entailed by a complete classical description, not the content of what they say in their experimental reports. That makes much more sense." One might interprete Bohr as a behaviorist, and believe that when he says:" we can tell others what we have done and what we have learned" he is merely speaking of a bunch of unconscious robots muttering sounds. Behaviour is *part* of the story: communication does require a behaviour. But to see *only* the behaviour is to miss the essence. The human activity in question is basically a process that is occurring in a realm of human conscious experiences. The physical theory is itself a collection of experiences, as are the empirical experiences that the observer reports. And these experiences are expressed in verbal statements that purport to represent certain facts about the world: the meaning of the content of the reports feeds into a behaviour that creates *articulated facts* in the realm of human consciousness. These statements are what logic deals with. So what is at issue here is the creation of the statements that logic manipulates, and also the very process by which the logicians and the mathematicians come to recognize and to manipulate the symbols that are the tools of their trade. So I am considering the problem from the meta level of the ontology within which the logical process---a human activity---occurs. I see this as the Bohrian level of analysis. So the entailment is not only a physical process but also a logical one, because a mathematically described situation in one domain, namely the domain of the actual physical reality---which due to the assumption of the correctness of the classical conception of nature is isomorphic to an infinite collection of overlapping possible human conceptualizations of it---becomes described within a verbal human language. ...... I said: >*Entailment* from the complete classical physical description plus the >Bohrian theory of experiment into the world of human experience means >the process of injecting articulated facts into the realm of human >discourse by means of the capacities of human observers to experience >macroscopic properties that: (1), are carried by the PAFs, >and (2), they have learned to recognize and report about. You said: "OK, I finally get this point. However, let me suggest that you find a way to rephrase your thesis. You really shouldnt call this 'entailment' without providing a MUCH more careful description of what you intend to mean, as this a COMPLETELY NEW kind of entailment. Roughly, A Bohr-entails B if it follows from A that someone will truthfully utter 'B'. (It might be interesting to investigate the logical properties of this, which seem most unusual. It's not transitive, for one thing, which rules out straightforward semantic approaches.)" It cannot be transitive because it is from the physical realm, as that realm is conceptualized in classical physics, to the realm of articulated statements. You said: "OK, now we can leave aside all the 'entailment' discussion ( I will just note from now on where you use this word in a potentially misleading way, but I understand what you mean by it, at last. I hope ...;-) "Now, however, I STILL can't detect the 'principled distinction' you insist on seeing somewhere. "Pat "[continued...]" Yes, you still are not seeing what I am seeing, for your words simply repeat things that I myself have already emphasized, and that are already encompassed within my thought: I have already stressed that we see the color of the leaf much on a par to experiencing its location and shape, and that we hear the pitch of the horn much on a par to sensing its location and shape. And I have already stressed that we can make errors in judgement as much about locations and shapes as about colors and pitches. In bringing up these points you are arguing against someone else in your past experience, or against some other position you may have heard expressed, not against me or mine. These differences/similarities, although often brought up by others, have nothing to do with the principled distinction that I am talking about. So I ask you to examine what *I* am saying. The principled distinction lies in the fact that classical physics has elected to erect itself (or the scientists such as Galileo, Descartes, Newton, & Maxwell who have created it have erected this conceptual edifice) *upon idealizations of our experiences of location and shape*, rejecting as elements of this edifice the other aspects of our experience that come to us all intertwined with, and more or less on a par with, our experiences of location and shape. Thus the description of the PAFs is in terms of idealizations of positions of stars and apples and cannon balls, familiar from our everyday (and clear-night) experiences. The experiences we have of the locations and shapes of objects are, as a matter of historical fact, used differently in the construction of classical physical theory than our experiences of color and pitch. I do not cite John Locke, and his primary and secondary qualitities, as an *authority* on what is true and correct about our understanding of nature, but he did correctly identify this particular features of the classical conception of nature that is, by now, so ingrained in the thinking of educated people as to render them almost unable to see it as a profound assumption that should be made explicit. This extraction and elevation of this particular aspect of our experience is certainly is AN aspect of the classical conception of nature, and I would say is, in fact, THE underlying presumption of the classical conception of nature. You asked: >>What singles out 'matching of spacetime forms' as the crucial kind of >>observation? Is this supposed to be an empirical claim about the way that >>experiments are conducted? It seems entirly ad-hoc and arbitrary, since the >>complete physical description predicts many other observable aspects of the >>world. I answered: > >The basic premise of the discussion is that the classical conception of >the physical world is correct. But this classical conception is based on >the conception or notion of *forms existing in spacetime*. You responded: "It is based on PAFs. These might be forms in spacetime, to be sure, but THESE forms cannot be perceived directly. They are just as inVISIBLE as sounds and smells (and degrees of happiness.) And on the classical conception, these spatiotemporal forms 'carry' all kinds of perceptual reports. So I repeat, what makes macroscopic spatiotemporal sightings different in principle (in the classical conception) from any other perceptual reports? (Answer: nothing.)" My point is that according to the classical conceptualization the physical world is built on spacetime forms that are idealizations of the *spacetime forms* that we experience in everyday life. It is not built on the other intertwined aspects of our experience. The spacetime forms of the PAFs, in the complete classical physical description on nature, entail, within that mathematical structure, large scale spacetime structures of visible (for example) size, and these large-scale structures are of the same conceptual kind as the large-scale spacetime structures that were idealized to form the theory. One can also build from the PAFs structures that have spacetime structures such as vibrations of collections of particles or of fields. But the amalgamations of forms from the spacetime forms of the PAFs never produce, by any direct rational mathematical construction, any of the things like the experiences of color or pitch that were excluded from the outset from the physical world as it was conceptualized in classical physics. You asked, above: " And on the classical conception, these spatiotemporal forms 'carry' all kinds of perceptual reports. So I repeat, what makes macroscopic spatiotemporal sightings different in principle (in the classical conception) from any other perceptual reports? (Answer: nothing.)" There seems to be here a basic disparity in our conceptions of what the `classical conception' of nature is, and, in particular, on what, *according to that conception*, is `carried' by the spaciotemporal forms. I say that according to the classical conception these spacetime forms `carry' only spacetime form: the spacetime forms are conceived of, in the classical conceptualization, simply as idealizations of our experiences of the spacetime locations and shapes of objects. Structures in space and time are what the classical physicist conceives the world to be built out of, and he conceives his experiences of shapes to be (with due allowance for small errors in perceptions) experiences of features of this physical world of spacetime structures. But his experiencing of a `color' is not the experiencing of the vibratory motion that in the classical conceptualization is the physical counterpart of the experienced color. Thus WITHIN THIS SPECIAL CONCEPTUALIZATION OF NATURE there is a principled difference between *physical* aspects of reality, which reside exclusively in spacetime form, conceptualized as idealizations of our experiences of the spacetime-form aspect of everyday experience, and the general phenomenal aspect of reality that includes, for example, our experiences of color and pitch, plus a vast amount more. What I call "the classical conception of nature" may be different from your notion of the meaning of this phrase. That is not what is important here: that is just a matter of definition. What is important is this: 1. *If* one accepts what I call "the classical conception of nature" as the way nature actually is then there is a principled distinction between the `physical' aspects of nature, which are built on idealizations of solely our experiences about the locations and spacetime shapes of physical objects, and the general `phenomenal' aspects of nature, which include such other things as `color', `pitch', and a whole lot more. 2. Certainly many educated people accept what I call "the classical conception of nature" as the scientific conception of nature without really recognizing that this is a very strong assumption, which they should make explicit, because it leads them to `intuitions' about the physical and phenomenal aspects of nature whose origin they fail to be fully aware of, and whose possible failure they should recognize. By explicilty recognizing the origin of their intuition they can formalize the basis of their prejudice, and thereby open the way to moving beyond it. You go on to object to my analysis point by point. But your point is always essentially the same, so let me pick one: I say: >one cannot *deduce* from the complete >classical physical description of nature which `color' will be experienced >when some observer looks at the leaf@@ You respond: "Until the point marked @@, this is just wrong. Color is an objective reflectance property, and the experience of color depends on it, the lighting conditions and the immediate optical history of the subject (for afterimages and the like.) Someone's experience of color is just as (physically) predictable as their experience of anything else." I am not talking about predicting! The issue that I am concerned with is what is logically entailed, within the classical conceptualization, by the complete classical physical description of nature. There is certainly no way of *deducing* the phenomenal feel of the color green from the vibratory quality of a light beam. But there IS a way of deducing the leaf-shapedness of the boy gardener's experience of the leaf from the leaf-shapedness of the amalgamation of PAFs that, according to the complete classical physical description of nature, constitute the physical leaf. This deduction is possible because the theoretical conceptualization of the leaf as it is represented in the complete classical physical description of nature is, by virtue of it origin, exactly the same kind of thing as the boy-gardener's experience of the leaf: the former is constructed from idealizations of experiences like the latter. But in the case of greeness some *rule of translation* is needed because experiencing vibratory frequency is not an idealization of experiencing greenness. This *rule of translation* may be establishable by empirical procedures, but it is not part of the classical conceptualization, and is not a necessary part of that conceptualization. On the other hand, the rule that allows the equating of leaf-shaped spacetime forms in the theoretical and empirical domains of experiences is a key part of the entire classical conception, because it is precisely this kind of identification of forms that, within this classical conceptualization, is the primitive basis of the comparison between theory and experiment. After the @@ I wrote: @@; for the complete classical physical >description is, by assumption, built exclusively out of properties like >the properies we experience when we experience spacetime forms, >not including properties like the properties we experience when we experience >colors. You said: "But after @@, you shift your ground to the trivial (again.) If we simply DEFINE 'classical physics' as excluding properties like the properties we experience when we experience colors, then of course these are not part of 'classical physics'. But that is a hollow victory indeed." You miss my point! I am not shifting my ground: I am giving the reason for the truth of the preceding sentence. It is true that I `define' the classical conceptualization, in the sense that I explain what it is. This particular conceptualization is, I believe, the classical-physics conceptualization as it is understood by physicists, and by many other educated thinkers. So it deservers a name, and also to be `defined' or characterized for the purpose of this discussion. It is also true that according to this definition, or characterization, the experience of colors is not part of `classical physics'. But his fact is not a victory. However, it is definitely something that ought to be recognized and appreciated by you. For, many of the people against whom you argue do, I am sure, accept this idea of nature, promulgated by classical physics, as a correct idea of the nature of physical reality, and within that conceptualization of physical reality the principled distinction is true, as you have admitted. So what you are actually asking them to do is to abandon the orthodox (I think this is a fair terms here) idea of nature put forth by classical physics. It would help communication if you would tell people that this is what you want them to do. You thought we had disposed of the *entailment* issue, but I think it is clear from the above that everything hangs on the fact that part of the classical-physics conceptualization is the notion that the spacetime forms of macroscopic amalgamations of PAFs into spacetime structures that are large enough to be seen (or felt etc.) can be experienced by human beings as the spacetime forms that, according to the classical conceptualization, they actually are (apart from small errors in perception). The analogous statement cannot be made for the quality of greenness, because the experience of greenness is not an experience of a property that, within the classical-physics conceptualization of nature, the leaf itself actually possesses (to some good approximation). You say: "But our experiences are NEVER `of the same kind' as the realities they represent." True! The sameness in kind is between the spacetime forms in our theoretical conceptualization of nature and the spacetime forms in our empirical experiences of physical objects. The sameness in kind arises there from the fact that the former are idealizations of the latter. But, according to the classical conceptualization, our classical-physics image of nature is a veridical picture of the physical reality itself, so the distinction between the reality itself and our veridical picture of it is not a source of real difficulty. You quote me: >experience the greenness of a leaf. Phenomenally experienced greenness >and phenomenally experienced spacetime form are DIFFERENT IN PRINCIPLE >in the context of their connections to the concepts used by classical >physicists to build their theoretical model of the physical world. And then say: "Well, I may simply have to defer to your historical suthority if this is really true. But its not a claim Ive seen anywhere else, and it doesnt square with almost everything Ive read about science before this century,the apparent behavior and published claims of scientists from Newton to Einstein, ar any other philosopher of science. Nowhere else have I seen this claim that our spatiotemporal perceptions are somehow more irreducibly physical than our other perceptions, or that physical models can only be connected to observations of this particular very special kind." Appeal to authority has no place this discussion. My argument is simply that classical physical theory is certainly built on particles and fields defined over spacetime, and that macroscopic spacetime structures then arise naturally from the equations of motion, and hence that physical objects can naturally acquire macroscopic spacetime form, but that this natural physical process, governed by the laws of classical physics, though it may entail vibratory motions of certain parts of the physical system, for example a leaf, does not entail as a physical property of that system itself, in addition to its, say, leaf-shaped form, also a property or quality that is structurally essentially the same as the quality of greenness that a (normal) human observer who looks at the leaf (under normal conditions) will experience as a property of the leaf. But the leaf will, according to this classical conceptualization, itself have a physical property or quality, namely its leaf-shapedness, that is structurally essentially the same as the quality of leaf-shapedness that a (normal) human observer who looks at the leaf (under normal conditions) will experience as a property of the leaf. The upshot here is that the experiences of greenness and of spacetime form do not enter in the same way into the classical-physics conceptualization of physical reality. This is because physical reality, according to the classical-physics conceptualization of it, is represented in its entirety in terms of motions of particles and fields, which can generate macroscopic spacetime forms, including vibrations, that can be essentially equated to observers' experiences of spacetime forms. And this provides the basic primitive bridge between theory and experiment. But there is nothing in the classical-physics representation of, say, the leaf, that can be `equated' (to a good approximation) to the observers' experiences of the greenness of the leaf. What corresponds in the leaf to the observers' experiences of greenness is something quite different, namely a vibration of the electromagnetic field. You quote me: >--- because >the conceptualization of the physical world provided by classical >physics is erected on our notions of spacetime form extracted from certain >sense experiences---we can empirically experience spacetime forms that >can be taken to be identifiable with spacetime aspects of the >complete classical physical description: moreover these spacetime forms >can, because of this identification and the precepts of the theory, be >considered to belong to both the physical and phenomenal worlds. Then you respond: "Yes to all this. But the key point, now, is that the physical form need not be experienced as a "similar" phenomenological form, whatever that could possibly mean. (Classical science tells us that a table is 'mostly' empty space, yet it looks and feels solid. Which is right? An old schoolboy's puzzle.) Physical vibrations cause neural firings which are experiences of sound; em vibrations similarly give rise to experiences of color. And certain large-scale assemblies reflect light in complex ways which we experience as shapes, positions and movements of objects. But our experiences of these 'forms' are no more similar IN KIND to the physical 'forms' than any other aspect of our phenomenology, and the complexity of the story that must be told in order to link them to the PAFs of reality is no less complex than that needed for colors, sounds, scents,... or, maybe, emotions. In fact, there is lots of evidence that it is considerably MORE complex." Yes, the basic issue is the connection of our brain activities to our experiences. I was responding to your attempt to say that there was no principled difference because spacetime form and e.g., greenness were on a par as properties of the objects. But that was a diversion: the real issue is indeed what is going on in our brains. But you say that the "neural firings... are experiences of sounds." According to classical physics, the firings of neurons are part of a physical world that is completely describable in terms of spacetime forms. It would seem that there is a problem in principle, here, because if one makes the claim that, within the classical-physics conceptualization, some complex neuronal firing pattern IS the experience of hearing a certain sound then one can ask how this claim is to be proved true within the framework of classical physics. We have seen how claims regarding the macrocscopic spacetime forms of physical objects, such as leaves, can be proved within the framework provided by the classical conceptualization. And that sort of argument can be carried over to the macroscopic spacetime properties of the conglomeration of neurons etc. that comprise the brain. This gives descriptions of `complex patterns of neuron firings', because these patterns ARE spacetime forms. But this kind of argument involves the spacetime structure of the object and the experience of that object by some observer who is observing that object through his senses. The situation regarding the experienced sound is fundamentally different for two reasons: (1), the sound that IS the particular pattern of neural firings is not an experience of a spacetime form. This characteristic of the experience was a crucial element in the former case: the capacity of human observers to `equate' the spacetime forms in their empirical experiences of sensed objects to the spacetime form of the object as it is conceptualized in classical physics was the key tool in the former case. (2), the relevant object in this case is not sensed by the relevant subject through the normal senses, as it was in the former case of the leaf. Thus the method for linking the physical and phenomenal used for the cases of the ordinary physical sciences does not carry over to this case: some new kind of `bridging principle' not needed in the normal physical sciences is apparently needed. I summarized: >The bottom line is that because the classical model world is built >exclusively upon idealizations and generalization of our sense experiences >about spacetime structures it is only these special kinds of empirical >experiences that can be conceived to be experiencings of the putative >physical world itself. That constitutes a PRINCIPLED DIFFERENCE between >these kinds of experiences and, for example, a phenomenal experience >of greenness. This difference biases the whole picture in the way >I have outlined above, and it prevents these latter sorts of empirical >experiences from being entailed by the classical physical model in the >way that empirical experiences of spacetime forms can. You replied: "At last I understand you; but I still don't agree. There is no difference here, because these experiences - EVEN ON THE CLASSICAL STORY - are not specially privileged. Your entire distinction is based not on a difference between kinds of physics, but upon a spurious distinction based on an outmoded view of perception. I suspect you have been misled by Bohr, who seems to have been influenced by the behaviorist views of perception and meaning that permeated the intellectual climate when he was writing. So you have failed to convert me. But thanks again for being so persistent!!" ---------------------- After all this, I am not letting you off so easily, my friend! Your claim that my whole view is not based on differences between kinds of physics is at variance with the fact that my whole view is based specifically upon the fact that the classical-physics conception that I discuss is based upon spacetime forms, and the exclusion from the physical part of reality of other kinds of possible realities. These spacetime forms are generalizations and idealizations of certain special aspects of the perceived world, but not of other aspects of the perceived world, which could be included in other physical theories. It is true that our understanding of `perception' can undergo changes. You my wish to take a strict functionalist view of perception that gives no status at all to the phenomenal (conscious/experiental) aspect of the perceptual reality. However, in your other writings you do not seem to go to the extreme of denying outright the existence of phenomenal reality. Rather you say there, and also here, that this reality IS some (functionally appropriate) activity in the brain. Also, at least in this discussion, you are in effect claiming that it is OK---for these considerations---to accept the classical-physics conceptualization of the brain. This claim is, indeed, the point at issue. There is, of course, a manifest *apparent* conflict between the two parts of your position: the classical-physics conceptualization claims that the brain is completely described in terms of spacetime forms, whereas your account of perception admits the existence of a phenomenal reality such as the experiencing of a sound, and this experiencing of a sound is something that was *not included* in the classical-physics conceptualization of the physical part of nature, which includes the brain. So there is the question of how something that IS, according to the classical-physics premise, a pattern of neuron firings, and a part of the classical-physics conceptualization of the physical part of nature, can BE an experiencing of a sound, which is among the things left out of the classical-physics conceptualization of the physical part of reality. According to the precepts of classical physics the pattern of firing IS the spacetime form of the corresponding PAFs, plus everything that is logically or mathematically entailed by these spacetime forms of the corresponding PAFs, but that's all. So you need, in principle, to show, at least in principle, how the existence of the phenomemal experiencing could be entailed by the spacetime form of the PAFs. Your claim seems to be this will arise from a modern way of understanding perception. It would not do to assert simply that the new understanding of perception asserts that the phenomenal reality IS the corresponding brain activity. For you have accepted here the classical-physics conceptualization of the brain, and hence of the brain activity, and that conceptualization must then be the starting point of, and a condition upon, any demonstration that this activity IS something described very differently. So I think you need to explain how a new understanding of perception could allow you to show how the classical-physics conceptualization of the brain activity can be shown to BE the phenomenal experiencing of, for example the musical note `high C', without introducing any bridging principle that is not contained in the classical-physics conceptualization of nature. Since you have said that my arguments against this does not depend upon "on a difference between kinds of physics" your demonstration should be based on the classical-physics conceptualization that I have described. If you can truly succeed in this task you will have not only moved our discussion forward very significantly, but greatly illuminated the entire field. Best wishes Henry